Seite - (000060) - in Disrupted Development and the Future of Inequality in the Age of Automation
Bild der Seite - (000060) -
Text der Seite - (000060) -
5 AUTOMATION AND STRUCTURAL TRANSFORMATION … 53
Summers (2013) considers a modification of the neoclassical
two-factor production function in which output is created via both a
complementary and a substitutive use of capital and labor (see for discus-
sion Atkinson & Bourguignon, 2014, p. xilx). Capital will be “deployed
in these two uses to the point where their marginal productivity is the
same” (Summers, 2013, p. 4) and a certain mix of capital and labor
will result. Summers highlights three implications of labor-saving capi-
tal use: (i) production opportunities are augmented and output thus
increases; (ii) wage rates fall; and (iii) returns to capital rise. Atkinson and
Bourguignon thus argue:
We can therefore tell a story of macroeconomic development where
initially the Solow model applies (…). A rising capital-labor ratio leads to
rising wages and a falling rate of return. Beyond a certain point however
(…) [labor-substituting capital use] begins to be positive. We then see
further growth in the economy, as capital per head rises (…). There is no
longer any gain to wage-earners, since they are increasingly being replaced
by robots/automation. What is more, the capital share rises, independently
of the elasticity of substitution. [The modified Solow model] highlights the
central distributional dilemma: that the benefits from growth now increas-
ingly accrue through rising profits. (Atkinson & Bourguignon, 2014, p. xilx)
In line with the argument of a distribution dilemma, Roine and
Waldenström (2014, p. 79)—though they are skeptical of any “mechan-
ical relationship between inequality and industrialization or technologi-
cal change”—argue that: “the technological development starting in the
1970s constitute[s] the start of a shift, not from agriculture to industry
as in Kuznets’ original story, but from traditional industry to an ICT-
intensive sector that initially rewards a small part of the population, but
eventually will spread, bringing inequality down.”1
There is thus a theoretical case that automation may be linked to
income inequality and wage stagnation. Is there also a case for it leading
to technological unemployment? The Solow model and its iterations sug-
gest greater output (i.e. supply) due to automation which should trans-
late into lower prices under conditions of competition. Lower prices in
turn should lead to greater quantities demanded which necessitate more
net employment of humans.
So, the net effect of using labor-saving technology could still be
labor-increasing domestically. It may, however, not be if we took the
Summers’ model to its extreme: this would mean assuming a perfectly
Disrupted Development and the Future of Inequality in the Age of Automation