Page - 223 - in The Complete Aristotle
Image of the Page - 223 -
Text of the Page - 223 -
no case. This rule is convertible for both destructive and constructive
purposes: for if, when we have suggested a division, the predicate appears to
hold in all or in a large number of cases, we may then claim that the other
should actually assert it universally, or else bring a negative instance to show
in what case it is not so: for if he does neither of these things, a refusal to
assert it will make him look absurd.
Another rule is to make definitions both of an accident and of its subject,
either of both separately or else of one of them, and then look and see if
anything untrue has been assumed as true in the definitions. Thus (e.g.) to see
if it is possible to wrong a god, ask what is ‘to wrong’? For if it be ‘to injure
deliberately’, clearly it is not possible for a god to be wronged: for it is
impossible that God should be injured. Again, to see if the good man is
jealous, ask who is the ‘jealous’ man and what is ‘jealousy’. For if ‘jealousy’
is pain at the apparent success of some well-behaved person, clearly the good
man is not jealous: for then he would be bad. Again, to see if the indignant
man is jealous, ask who each of them is: for then it will be obvious whether
the statement is true or false; e.g. if he is ‘jealous’ who grieves at the
successes of the good, and he is ‘indignant’ who grieves at the successes of
the evil, then clearly the indignant man would not be jealous. A man should
substitute definitions also for the terms contained in his definitions, and not
stop until he comes to a familiar term: for often if the definition be rendered
whole, the point at issue is not cleared up, whereas if for one of the terms
used in the definition a definition be stated, it becomes obvious.
Moreover, a man should make the problem into a proposition for himself,
and then bring a negative instance against it: for the negative instance will be
a ground of attack upon the assertion. This rule is very nearly the same as the
rule to look into cases where a predicate has been attributed or denied
universally: but it differs in the turn of the argument.
Moreover, you should define what kind of things should be called as most
men call them, and what should not. For this is useful both for establishing
and for overthrowing a view: e.g. you should say that we ought to use our
terms to mean the same things as most people mean by them, but when we
ask what kind of things are or are not of such and such a kind, we should not
here go with the multitude: e.g. it is right to call ‘healthy’ whatever tends to
produce health, as do most men: but in saying whether the object before us
tends to produce health or not, we should adopt the language no longer of the
multitude but of the doctor.
<
div id=“section21” class=“section” title=“3”>
223
back to the
book The Complete Aristotle"
The Complete Aristotle
- Title
- The Complete Aristotle
- Author
- Aristotle
- Date
- ~322 B.C.
- Language
- English
- License
- PD
- Size
- 21.0 x 29.7 cm
- Pages
- 2328
- Keywords
- Philosophy, Antique, Philosophie, Antike, Dialogues, Metaphysik, Metaphysics, Ideologie, Ideology, Englisch
- Categories
- Geisteswissenschaften
- International
Table of contents
- Part 1; Logic (Organon) 3
- Categories 4
- On Interpretation 34
- Prior Analytics, Book I 56
- Prior Analytics, Book II 113
- Posterior Analytics, Book I 149
- Posterior Analytics, Book II 193
- Topics, Book I 218
- Topics, Book II 221
- Topics, Book III 237
- Topics, Book IV 248
- Topics, Book V 266
- Topics, Book VI 291
- Topics, Book VII 317
- Topics, Book VIII 326
- On Sophistical Refutations 348
- Part 2; Universal Physics 396
- Physics, Book I 397
- Physics, Book II 415
- Physics, Book III 432
- Physics, Book IV 449
- Physics, Book V 481
- Physics, Book VI 496
- Physics, Book VII 519
- Physics, Book VIII 533
- On the Heavens, Book I 570
- On the Heavens, Book II 599
- On the Heavens, Book III 624
- On the Heavens, Book IV 640
- On Generation and Corruption, Book I 651
- On Generation and Corruption, Book II 685
- Meteorology, Book I 707
- Meteorology, Book II 733
- Meteorology, Book III 760
- Meteorology, Book IV 773
- Part 3; Human Physics 795
- On the Soul, Book I 796
- On the Soul, Book II 815
- On the Soul, Book III 840
- On Sense and the Sensible 861
- On Memory and Reminiscence 889
- On Sleep and Sleeplessness 899
- On Dreams 909
- On Prophesying by Dreams 918
- On Longevity and the Shortness of Life 923
- On Youth, Old Age, Life and Death, and Respiration 929
- Part 4; Animal Physics 952
- The History of Animals, Book I 953
- The History of Animals, Book II translated 977
- The History of Animals, Book III 1000
- The History of Animals, Book IV 1029
- The History of Animals, Book V 1056
- The History of Animals, Book VI 1094
- The History of Animals, Book VII 1135
- The History of Animals, Book VIII 1150
- The History of Animals, Book IX 1186
- On the Parts of Animals, Book I 1234
- On the Parts of Animals, Book II 1249
- On the Parts of Animals, Book III 1281
- On the Parts of Animals, Book IV 1311
- On the Motion of Animals 1351
- On the Gait of Animals 1363
- On the Generation of Animals, Book I 1381
- On the Generation of Animals, Book II 1412
- On the Generation of Animals, Book III 1444
- On the Generation of Animals, Book IV 1469
- On the Generation of Animals, Book V 1496
- Part 5; Metaphysics 1516
- Part 6; Ethics and Politics 1748
- Nicomachean Ethics, Book I 1749
- Nicomachean Ethics, Book II 1766
- Nicomachean Ethics, Book III 1779
- Nicomachean Ethics, Book IV 1799
- Nicomachean Ethics, Book V 1817
- Nicomachean Ethics, Book VI 1836
- Nicomachean Ethics, Book VII 1851
- Nicomachean Ethics, Book VIII 1872
- Nicomachean Ethics, Book IX 1890
- Nicomachean Ethics, Book X 1907
- Politics, Book I 1925
- Politics, Book II 1943
- Politics, Book III 1970
- Politics, Book IV 1997
- Politics, Book V 2023
- Politics, Book VI 2053
- Politics, Book VII 2065
- Politics, Book VIII 2091
- The Athenian Constitution 2102
- Part 7; Aesthetic Writings 2156