Page - 23 - in The Priority of Locomotion in Aristotle’s Physics
Image of the Page - 23 -
Text of the Page - 23 -
argued in his commentary on De Caelo that this was the right way of divid-
ing the Physics.32
But there appears to be a problem with this division. It looks as though it
is compatible with all the statements about the arrangement of the books
that were presented by Simplicius in order to support his and Andronicus’
view; all but one: as we have seen, Damas reports that according to Eude-
mus the treatise On Change consists of three books. Dividing the Physics
after Book IV however, would imply that the work On Change consists of
Books V–VIII, i.e. of four rather than three books. Yet, there is another
statement by Eudemus which tells us something about the structure of our
Physics. Eudemus who, as already mentioned, was a direct disciple of Aris-
totle, did not consider Book VII to be a genuine part of the Physics.33
Ancient commentators and modern scholars, too, for several reasons take
Book VII to be a later misplacement of either a formerly independent trea-
tise, an earlier version of Book VIII, or some collection of notes on the topic
of change.34 However, it is correct to say that Book VII is related in a cer-
tain way to Book VIII35 and, as it deals with change in general, rather
belongs to the part of the Physics which was called On Change than On Nat-
ure. The mere fact that it is related to Phys. VIII in content, however,
implies neither that Aristotle himself considered it to be a necessary part of
the treatise On Change, nor that he intended to place it between Book VI
and VIII. For, as I will show, Book VII interrupts the line of thought that
connects VI and VIII and therefore certainly was not a part of the treatise
On Change, although the points discussed in Book VII clearly are closely
connected to those dealt with in the On Change.36 This then lead Simplicius
32 See In Cael. 1, 226, 19–23, where Simplicius claims that Aristotle called the first four
books On Principles and the remaining four On Change (περὶ ἀρχῶν τὰ τέσσαρα πρῶτα
βιβλία τὴς Φυσικῆς ἀκροάσεως, ὥσπερ τὰ λοιπὰ τέσσαρα περὶ κινήσεως).
33 See Simplicius In Phys. 7, 1036, 11–15. See also Jaeger (1955), 312, Brunschwig (1991),
27, and Barnes (1997), 61.
34 According to Simplicius, who himself holds that VII does not fit in its context, Alexan-
der, Eudemus, and Themistius also seem to have thought this way (In Phys. 7, 1036, 8–17)
(and, indeed, Themistius’ paraphrasis of Phys. VII is rather short in comparison to that of the
other books). See also Ross (1936), 15–17, Mansion (1946), 14–15, Jaeger (1955), 312, Wagner
(1967), 275, and Brunschwig (1991), 27, 31, for the claim that Physics VII must be a misplace-
ment.
35 See Waterlow (1982), 236, n.22, and Wardy (1990), 114–116, who argue that Physics
VII provides support for an assumption on which the theory developed in Phys. VIII 1–6
relies. One could further add that VII 2 is the only place where Aristotle systematically dis-
cusses the claim that the non-substantial kinds of change presuppose that the changer and
the subject of the change come into contact, an assumption clearly presupposed by the first of
the five arguments for the priority claim (see section 3.3, esp. p.50–51).
36 For instance Book VI ends with the remark that it remains to be shown that there is
The arrangement of the Physics 23
ISBN Print: 9783525253069 — ISBN E-Book: 9783647253060
© 2014, Vandenhoeck & Ruprecht GmbH & Co. KG, Göttingen
The Priority of Locomotion in Aristotle’s Physics
- Title
- The Priority of Locomotion in Aristotle’s Physics
- Author
- Sebastian Odzuck
- Editor
- Dorothea Frede
- Gisela Striker
- Publisher
- Vandenhoeck & Ruprecht GmbH & Co
- Date
- 2014
- Language
- English
- License
- CC BY-NC-ND 4.0
- ISBN
- 9783647253060
- Size
- 15.5 x 23.2 cm
- Pages
- 238
- Categories
- Geisteswissenschaften
- Naturwissenschaften Physik
Table of contents
- Acknowledgements 9
- 1. Introduction 10
- 2. The importance of the primary kind of change 14
- 3. Change in quality and quantity of living beings depends on loco-motion, but not vice versa 42
- 4. Locomotion necessarily accompanies each of the other kinds of change, but not vice versa 71
- 4.1 Overview 71
- 4.2 What changes in quantity changes with respect to place 73
- 4.3 What undergoes generation or corruption changes with respect to place 89
- 4.4 What changes in quality changes with respect to place 98
- 4.4.1 Overview 98
- 4.4.2 What does it mean that condensation and rarefaction are principles of quality? 100
- 4.4.3 Every alteration involves a change in the four basic qualities 104
- 4.4.4 Every change in the four basic qualities involves con- densation or rarefaction 108
- 4.4.5 Condensation and rarefaction are forms of aggregation and segregation 110
- 4.4.6 What changes in quality changes with respect to place 112
- 4.4.7 Conclusion 113
- 4.5 Conclusion 113
- 5. All changes depend on the first locomotion, but not vice versa 115
- 6. Locomotion has temporal priority 144
- 6.1 Overview 144
- 6.2 Locomotion has priority in time, since it is the only change eternals can undergo 146
- 6.3 Objection: Locomotion is the last of all changes in perishable things 148
- 6.4 Coming to be presupposes an earlier locomotion 150
- 6.5 The locomotion of the sun as a cause of generation 154
- 6.6 Conclusion 162
- 7. Locomotion is prior in essence 164
- 7.1 Locomotion is prior in essence, since it is last in coming to be 164
- 7.2 Locomotion alone preserves its subject’s essence 186
- 7.2.1 Overview 186
- 7.2.2 Locomotion does not change its subject’s being 188
- 7.2.3 Locomotion preserves its subject’s essence best 190
- 7.2.4 Making x depart from its essence by being part of a change in essence? 195
- 7.2.5 Change in quality or quantity in principle may result in a change in essence 202
- 7.3 Conclusion: Locomotion’s priority in essence 207
- 8. Conclusion 211
- Bibliography 220
- List of Abbreviations 223
- Index Locorum 221
- Index Nominum 223
- Index Rerum 221