Page - 54 - in The Priority of Locomotion in Aristotle’s Physics
Image of the Page - 54 -
Text of the Page - 54 -
for after all magnitude (μέγεθος) in Met. V 13 in general is defined as a
quantum (ποσόν) that is measurable and can be divided into continuous
(συνεχές) parts.38 Things that have a magnitude and can change with
respect to it would then include for instance all kinds of living organisms,
but also things like a lump of clay, a stalactite or a certain quantum of water
or air. According to this general definition of magnitude—and this seems to
be the point of the aforementioned criticism—all cases in which such things
change with respect to their size would count as instances of a change in
magnitude, and not only the special case of growth and diminution in living
beings. But if Aristotle’s argument really is supposed to show that locomo-
tion is prior to any change in magnitude, but only presents reasons for this
being true in the special case of growth and diminution in animals, then the
argument, it seems, fails. That Aristotle’s argument refers solely to changes
in magnitude of living beings is clear not only from what is said in Phys.
VIII 7, but also from the fact that the characterisation of growth there is a
short version of what is stated in GC I 5 and parts of de An II 4.39 This, it
appears, would be highly problematic, as it is far from clear, not to say
wrong, that all instances of change with respect to magnitude in general—
including the cases I just mentioned—occur in the way Aristotle explained
growth in the first argument for the primacy of locomotion. Suppose, for
instance, a puddle increases in size and becomes larger as it rains. To put it
more generally, in this case a portion of water changes with respect to its
magnitude by more water being added to it. In this case there certainly is
no need for the raindrops that are added to the puddle to undergo an altera-
tion in the way presented in the argument in order to become a part of the
puddle and to be absorbed by the whole in the same way that food is trans-
formed and integrated into the body. Another example which shows the
same would be that of a river which changes in magnitude over the year: in
but rather more with respect to its role in nature (φυσικώτερον), which means in a sense
that excludes other cases of change in magnitude. Graham (1999), 121, in this argument also
understands αὔξησις in the restricted biological sense, but does not seem to think that this is
a problem.
38 See Met. V 13, 1020a7–11.
39 This for instance is obvious from the fact that in de An. II 4 Aristotle explains one of
the essential characteristics of growth in general, namely that it occurs in one sense by what is
like, in another sense by what is unlike, with reference to the fact that the food which is unlike
at the beginning by being digested becomes like that to which it is added (see my discussion
in section 3.2.1 and de An. II 4, 416b6–7). That the account of growth presented in GC I 5 is
restricted to cases of the growth of living organisms, although it is also considered as a change
in magnitude there (320a13–14) is pointed out for instance by Joachim (1922), 110, who
argues that in GC I 5 the use of αὔξησις only refers to growth of ἔμψυχα, and Code (2004),
171, who claims that growth is treated in GC I 5 not as increase in size in general but rather
as a “kind of natural phenomenon”.
54 Change in quality and quantity of living beings
ISBN Print: 9783525253069 — ISBN E-Book: 9783647253060
© 2014, Vandenhoeck & Ruprecht GmbH & Co. KG, Göttingen
The Priority of Locomotion in Aristotle’s Physics
- Title
- The Priority of Locomotion in Aristotle’s Physics
- Author
- Sebastian Odzuck
- Editor
- Dorothea Frede
- Gisela Striker
- Publisher
- Vandenhoeck & Ruprecht GmbH & Co
- Date
- 2014
- Language
- English
- License
- CC BY-NC-ND 4.0
- ISBN
- 9783647253060
- Size
- 15.5 x 23.2 cm
- Pages
- 238
- Categories
- Geisteswissenschaften
- Naturwissenschaften Physik
Table of contents
- Acknowledgements 9
- 1. Introduction 10
- 2. The importance of the primary kind of change 14
- 3. Change in quality and quantity of living beings depends on loco-motion, but not vice versa 42
- 4. Locomotion necessarily accompanies each of the other kinds of change, but not vice versa 71
- 4.1 Overview 71
- 4.2 What changes in quantity changes with respect to place 73
- 4.3 What undergoes generation or corruption changes with respect to place 89
- 4.4 What changes in quality changes with respect to place 98
- 4.4.1 Overview 98
- 4.4.2 What does it mean that condensation and rarefaction are principles of quality? 100
- 4.4.3 Every alteration involves a change in the four basic qualities 104
- 4.4.4 Every change in the four basic qualities involves con- densation or rarefaction 108
- 4.4.5 Condensation and rarefaction are forms of aggregation and segregation 110
- 4.4.6 What changes in quality changes with respect to place 112
- 4.4.7 Conclusion 113
- 4.5 Conclusion 113
- 5. All changes depend on the first locomotion, but not vice versa 115
- 6. Locomotion has temporal priority 144
- 6.1 Overview 144
- 6.2 Locomotion has priority in time, since it is the only change eternals can undergo 146
- 6.3 Objection: Locomotion is the last of all changes in perishable things 148
- 6.4 Coming to be presupposes an earlier locomotion 150
- 6.5 The locomotion of the sun as a cause of generation 154
- 6.6 Conclusion 162
- 7. Locomotion is prior in essence 164
- 7.1 Locomotion is prior in essence, since it is last in coming to be 164
- 7.2 Locomotion alone preserves its subject’s essence 186
- 7.2.1 Overview 186
- 7.2.2 Locomotion does not change its subject’s being 188
- 7.2.3 Locomotion preserves its subject’s essence best 190
- 7.2.4 Making x depart from its essence by being part of a change in essence? 195
- 7.2.5 Change in quality or quantity in principle may result in a change in essence 202
- 7.3 Conclusion: Locomotion’s priority in essence 207
- 8. Conclusion 211
- Bibliography 220
- List of Abbreviations 223
- Index Locorum 221
- Index Nominum 223
- Index Rerum 221