Page - 55 - in The Priority of Locomotion in Aristotle’s Physics
Image of the Page - 55 -
Text of the Page - 55 -
spring, for instance, when the snow is melting, rivers usually become
broader and in this sense increase in size. For once the snow starts to melt,
additional water may flow into the rivers, making them become larger. Yet,
as in the case of the enlargement of the puddle, the water which flows into
the river does not have to undergo any sort of alteration in order to become
a part of the river.40 As a last example of an increase in quantity that does
not involve an alteration of that which is added, one could also refer to the
case of blowing up a balloon: the more air I blow into the balloon, the more
its size will increase. Yet, the air which I blow into the balloon does not have
to alter in order to become a part of the air in the balloon. More examples
like this could be added.
Accordingly, I think it is correct that Aristotle in the first argument
understands change in magnitude, i.e. growth and diminution, as the kind
of change in size that living things undergo. However, this seems not only
true for this passage, but for many others as well. As I see it, Aristotle in
general considers change in quantity not merely as some process involving
increase and decrease in size, but primarily as such cases in which a living
organism grows and diminishes. For, besides the fact that it is clearly stated
in the De Anima that only things that have a soul, i.e. living things, can be
subject to growth and diminution, that is, change in quantity, in the proper
sense, this is also what is implied by the way in which growth and diminu-
tion are described in Phys. V 2 and VI 10. For in the first of these two pas-
sages change with respect to quantity (κατὰ τὸ ποσόν) is defined as
growth, i.e. change “to the complete magnitude” (εἰς τὸ τέλειον μέγεθος
αὔξησις), and as diminution, i.e. change away from this magnitude (ἐκ
τούτου φθίσις).41 In Phys. VI 10 something more is added, for here it is
stated that growth aims at reaching the complete magnitude that is specific
to the nature (φύσις) of the respective thing, while diminution is a change
away from this magnitude.42 Both passages clearly indicate that change in
quantity for Aristotle is not merely becoming larger or smaller in some
sense, but rather needs to be understood primarily as a change with respect
to a certain goal and nature. Yet, one certainly cannot say that whatever
40 The melting of the snow, of course, involves an alteration, namely the heating of a por-
tion of snow, yet, when what was formerly snow and now is water flows into the river, the
portion of water does not have to change in quality; it does not matter whether the increase
in size occurs by the water from molten snow, or by rain, or by a factory letting its effluent
flow into a nearby river—whenever water is added to a river, i.e. a large portion of water, it
does not have to alter beforehand.
41 See Phys. VIII 7, 260a29–32.
42 αὐξήσεως μὲν γὰρ τὸ πέρας τοῦ κατὰ τὴν οἰκείαν φύσιν τελείου μεγέθους,
φθίσεως δὲ ἡ τούτου ἔκστασις. Phys. VI 10, 241a33–b2: “the limit of growth is to be found
in the complete magnitude proper to the nature of the thing, while the limit of diminution is
the loss of such magnitude.” (Transl. Hardie & Gaye with mod.).
Does locomotion precede all occurrences of change in quantity? 55
ISBN Print: 9783525253069 — ISBN E-Book: 9783647253060
© 2014, Vandenhoeck & Ruprecht GmbH & Co. KG, Göttingen
The Priority of Locomotion in Aristotle’s Physics
- Title
- The Priority of Locomotion in Aristotle’s Physics
- Author
- Sebastian Odzuck
- Editor
- Dorothea Frede
- Gisela Striker
- Publisher
- Vandenhoeck & Ruprecht GmbH & Co
- Date
- 2014
- Language
- English
- License
- CC BY-NC-ND 4.0
- ISBN
- 9783647253060
- Size
- 15.5 x 23.2 cm
- Pages
- 238
- Categories
- Geisteswissenschaften
- Naturwissenschaften Physik
Table of contents
- Acknowledgements 9
- 1. Introduction 10
- 2. The importance of the primary kind of change 14
- 3. Change in quality and quantity of living beings depends on loco-motion, but not vice versa 42
- 4. Locomotion necessarily accompanies each of the other kinds of change, but not vice versa 71
- 4.1 Overview 71
- 4.2 What changes in quantity changes with respect to place 73
- 4.3 What undergoes generation or corruption changes with respect to place 89
- 4.4 What changes in quality changes with respect to place 98
- 4.4.1 Overview 98
- 4.4.2 What does it mean that condensation and rarefaction are principles of quality? 100
- 4.4.3 Every alteration involves a change in the four basic qualities 104
- 4.4.4 Every change in the four basic qualities involves con- densation or rarefaction 108
- 4.4.5 Condensation and rarefaction are forms of aggregation and segregation 110
- 4.4.6 What changes in quality changes with respect to place 112
- 4.4.7 Conclusion 113
- 4.5 Conclusion 113
- 5. All changes depend on the first locomotion, but not vice versa 115
- 6. Locomotion has temporal priority 144
- 6.1 Overview 144
- 6.2 Locomotion has priority in time, since it is the only change eternals can undergo 146
- 6.3 Objection: Locomotion is the last of all changes in perishable things 148
- 6.4 Coming to be presupposes an earlier locomotion 150
- 6.5 The locomotion of the sun as a cause of generation 154
- 6.6 Conclusion 162
- 7. Locomotion is prior in essence 164
- 7.1 Locomotion is prior in essence, since it is last in coming to be 164
- 7.2 Locomotion alone preserves its subject’s essence 186
- 7.2.1 Overview 186
- 7.2.2 Locomotion does not change its subject’s being 188
- 7.2.3 Locomotion preserves its subject’s essence best 190
- 7.2.4 Making x depart from its essence by being part of a change in essence? 195
- 7.2.5 Change in quality or quantity in principle may result in a change in essence 202
- 7.3 Conclusion: Locomotion’s priority in essence 207
- 8. Conclusion 211
- Bibliography 220
- List of Abbreviations 223
- Index Locorum 221
- Index Nominum 223
- Index Rerum 221