Page - 120 - in The Priority of Locomotion in Aristotle’s Physics
Image of the Page - 120 -
Text of the Page - 120 -
ciple of Aristotle’s theory of change, that a change that is explicitly charac-
terised as continuous in our passage is contrasted with another that suppo-
sedly is not, while at the same time both changes by means of the adverbial
form of συνεχές are said to exist continuously (συνεχῶς).14 For a change
that would be eternal in virtue of being composed of some other changes
differs from the first one precisely in its not being continuous, and this
seems to be the reason for preferring option (1) to option (2). In order to
make sense of the argument as a whole one certainly needs to understand
what exactly Aristotle means by these statements and in what way he is cor-
rect in making them.
Part of the difficulty lies in the fact that Aristotle here (but also in other
places15) in addition to the two uses of the term ‘change’ already men-
tioned, i.e. as a mass term and a count noun, also implicitly presupposes
two different notions of the word ‘change’ (κίνησις), namely a wider and a
narrower notion, when it is used in the sense of a count noun. One needs to
be aware of this difference in order to make sense of the third argument,
because it is due to the fact that these two notions seem to be applied here
that it is at all possible to confront the case of a continuous change with
what seems to be a non-continuous one. The two notions of ‘change’ are
these: on the one hand, the term ‘change’ may refer to a change that is con-
tinuous, i.e. whose (potential) parts form one whole change in virtue of
their limits being one and the same. This kind of change is a change in the
strict sense of the word, since usually for Aristotle every change must be
continuous—in fact it is this very feature which allows Aristotle to reject
Zeno’s paradoxes in Phys. VI and thereby to make it possible to treat
change as a phenomenon that is accessible to scientific inquiry.
On the other hand, there is a notion of change that is of a wider scope
and which seems to encompass phenomena that we would also call ‘change’
in our everyday language, but that according to the strict understanding
presented above would not count as one continuous change. The second
way in which change (in the sense of the mass term) may be said to be eter-
nal, i.e. by there being an eternal change that is composed of a number of
individual succeeding changes so to speak, is an example of Aristotle’s use
of the wider notion of change. In contrast to the strict sense, such a change
are they supposed to touch? An explanation of this necessarily will need to refer to the differ-
ent factors that determine a change, i.e. the subject, the realm (e.g. place or quality), and the
time with respect to which the change occurs.
14 Therefore, Graham (1999), 125, is right when he notes that the use of συνεχῶς, at least
at first glance, “as a modifier for cosmic motion is potentially misleading” because Aristotle
“does not intend this qualification by itself to entail continuous motion” contrary to what one
might think.
15 See for instance also Phys. V 4 (see p.121, n.17).
120 All changes depend on the first locomotion, but not vice versa
ISBN Print: 9783525253069 — ISBN E-Book: 9783647253060
© 2014, Vandenhoeck & Ruprecht GmbH & Co. KG, Göttingen
The Priority of Locomotion in Aristotle’s Physics
- Title
- The Priority of Locomotion in Aristotle’s Physics
- Author
- Sebastian Odzuck
- Editor
- Dorothea Frede
- Gisela Striker
- Publisher
- Vandenhoeck & Ruprecht GmbH & Co
- Date
- 2014
- Language
- English
- License
- CC BY-NC-ND 4.0
- ISBN
- 9783647253060
- Size
- 15.5 x 23.2 cm
- Pages
- 238
- Categories
- Geisteswissenschaften
- Naturwissenschaften Physik
Table of contents
- Acknowledgements 9
- 1. Introduction 10
- 2. The importance of the primary kind of change 14
- 3. Change in quality and quantity of living beings depends on loco-motion, but not vice versa 42
- 4. Locomotion necessarily accompanies each of the other kinds of change, but not vice versa 71
- 4.1 Overview 71
- 4.2 What changes in quantity changes with respect to place 73
- 4.3 What undergoes generation or corruption changes with respect to place 89
- 4.4 What changes in quality changes with respect to place 98
- 4.4.1 Overview 98
- 4.4.2 What does it mean that condensation and rarefaction are principles of quality? 100
- 4.4.3 Every alteration involves a change in the four basic qualities 104
- 4.4.4 Every change in the four basic qualities involves con- densation or rarefaction 108
- 4.4.5 Condensation and rarefaction are forms of aggregation and segregation 110
- 4.4.6 What changes in quality changes with respect to place 112
- 4.4.7 Conclusion 113
- 4.5 Conclusion 113
- 5. All changes depend on the first locomotion, but not vice versa 115
- 6. Locomotion has temporal priority 144
- 6.1 Overview 144
- 6.2 Locomotion has priority in time, since it is the only change eternals can undergo 146
- 6.3 Objection: Locomotion is the last of all changes in perishable things 148
- 6.4 Coming to be presupposes an earlier locomotion 150
- 6.5 The locomotion of the sun as a cause of generation 154
- 6.6 Conclusion 162
- 7. Locomotion is prior in essence 164
- 7.1 Locomotion is prior in essence, since it is last in coming to be 164
- 7.2 Locomotion alone preserves its subject’s essence 186
- 7.2.1 Overview 186
- 7.2.2 Locomotion does not change its subject’s being 188
- 7.2.3 Locomotion preserves its subject’s essence best 190
- 7.2.4 Making x depart from its essence by being part of a change in essence? 195
- 7.2.5 Change in quality or quantity in principle may result in a change in essence 202
- 7.3 Conclusion: Locomotion’s priority in essence 207
- 8. Conclusion 211
- Bibliography 220
- List of Abbreviations 223
- Index Locorum 221
- Index Nominum 223
- Index Rerum 221