Seite - 81 - in The Priority of Locomotion in Aristotle’s Physics
Bild der Seite - 81 -
Text der Seite - 81 -
the sense that they no longer stand in the same relation to the other parts.
The inner spatial order of the different parts changes in virtue of the whole
undergoing a change in quantity—after all, this is exactly what growth and
diminution are about. This, however, is the crucial difference between
something that undergoes growth and diminution and something that
undergoes a change in place as a whole, i.e. locomotion: all of the latter’s
parts change in place but nevertheless their inner spatial order and their
relation to each other remain exactly the same.
In this sense, for x to change in place as a whole means that all of its parts
must change in place while remaining in the same inner spatial order, so to
speak. In merely undergoing locomotion, a given part of the revolving
sphere will always remain in the same relation to the other parts of the
sphere. This is the reason why the sphere remains in a place of equal size,
although all of its parts are changing in place, and why Aristotle contrasted
this example with something that undergoes growth that does not change
in place as a whole, but only with respect to its parts. The sphere retains its
inner structure and the relation of its parts. This, however, is not only the
case for the revolving sphere, but also for any other object that in under-
going one single motion changes from place A to B as a whole. Suppose I
move a pen that I am holding in my hand from left to right in one perfect
rectilinear motion: each part of it moves from its former to its new equal-
sized place without changing its relation to any of the other parts, i.e. the
pen changes in place as a whole. Since with growth and diminution the
situation is essentially different, Aristotle is correct to claim that both in a
sense are kinds of change in place, though only insofar as the parts of their
respective subjects move.
4.2.4 A possible objection
But is it really adequate to say that when x undergoes locomotion, the rela-
tion of its parts always remains the same? There are many cases in which
something undergoes a change in place as a whole, yet at the very same time
its parts nonetheless change their relation to each other, and therefore seem
to show that my interpretation must be wrong. The following case for
instance appears to provide just such a counterexample. Suppose I walk
from my office to the cafeteria to get a cup of tea. I do so by moving my
legs. In the process of walking, however, the relation between my body’s
parts does of course change, although I certainly undergo a change in place
as a whole and not only with respect to some of my parts!
I do not think that this is a problem for the interpretation of change in
place as a whole that I have presented and the claims connected to it. There-
fore, I will now discuss two strategies that might enable one to provide an
What changes in quantity changes with respect to place 81
ISBN Print: 9783525253069 — ISBN E-Book: 9783647253060
© 2014, Vandenhoeck & Ruprecht GmbH & Co. KG, Göttingen
The Priority of Locomotion in Aristotle’s Physics
- Titel
- The Priority of Locomotion in Aristotle’s Physics
- Autor
- Sebastian Odzuck
- Herausgeber
- Dorothea Frede
- Gisela Striker
- Verlag
- Vandenhoeck & Ruprecht GmbH & Co
- Datum
- 2014
- Sprache
- englisch
- Lizenz
- CC BY-NC-ND 4.0
- ISBN
- 9783647253060
- Abmessungen
- 15.5 x 23.2 cm
- Seiten
- 238
- Kategorien
- Geisteswissenschaften
- Naturwissenschaften Physik
Inhaltsverzeichnis
- Acknowledgements 9
- 1. Introduction 10
- 2. The importance of the primary kind of change 14
- 3. Change in quality and quantity of living beings depends on loco-motion, but not vice versa 42
- 4. Locomotion necessarily accompanies each of the other kinds of change, but not vice versa 71
- 4.1 Overview 71
- 4.2 What changes in quantity changes with respect to place 73
- 4.3 What undergoes generation or corruption changes with respect to place 89
- 4.4 What changes in quality changes with respect to place 98
- 4.4.1 Overview 98
- 4.4.2 What does it mean that condensation and rarefaction are principles of quality? 100
- 4.4.3 Every alteration involves a change in the four basic qualities 104
- 4.4.4 Every change in the four basic qualities involves con- densation or rarefaction 108
- 4.4.5 Condensation and rarefaction are forms of aggregation and segregation 110
- 4.4.6 What changes in quality changes with respect to place 112
- 4.4.7 Conclusion 113
- 4.5 Conclusion 113
- 5. All changes depend on the first locomotion, but not vice versa 115
- 6. Locomotion has temporal priority 144
- 6.1 Overview 144
- 6.2 Locomotion has priority in time, since it is the only change eternals can undergo 146
- 6.3 Objection: Locomotion is the last of all changes in perishable things 148
- 6.4 Coming to be presupposes an earlier locomotion 150
- 6.5 The locomotion of the sun as a cause of generation 154
- 6.6 Conclusion 162
- 7. Locomotion is prior in essence 164
- 7.1 Locomotion is prior in essence, since it is last in coming to be 164
- 7.2 Locomotion alone preserves its subject’s essence 186
- 7.2.1 Overview 186
- 7.2.2 Locomotion does not change its subject’s being 188
- 7.2.3 Locomotion preserves its subject’s essence best 190
- 7.2.4 Making x depart from its essence by being part of a change in essence? 195
- 7.2.5 Change in quality or quantity in principle may result in a change in essence 202
- 7.3 Conclusion: Locomotion’s priority in essence 207
- 8. Conclusion 211
- Bibliography 220
- List of Abbreviations 223
- Index Locorum 221
- Index Nominum 223
- Index Rerum 221