Web-Books
im Austria-Forum
Austria-Forum
Web-Books
Geisteswissenschaften
The Priority of Locomotion in Aristotle’s Physics
Seite - 51 -
  • Benutzer
  • Version
    • Vollversion
    • Textversion
  • Sprache
    • Deutsch
    • English - Englisch

Seite - 51 - in The Priority of Locomotion in Aristotle’s Physics

Bild der Seite - 51 -

Bild der Seite - 51 - in The Priority of Locomotion in Aristotle’s Physics

Text der Seite - 51 -

things are touching each other, and indeed the relation of two things touch- ing (ἅπτεσθαι) each other is defined in Phys. V 3 with respect to the things’ extremes being situated together.30 But for two things to come into contact implies that they have to come closer to each other, and accordingly either one or both of them have to change place. It is for this reason that Aristotle is able to state that the alterer “does not [always] hold the same relation [to what is altered], but sometimes is nearer and sometimes farther away from what is altered.”31 In order for that which is hot to impart its heat to some other thing that is cold, the two things have to move towards each other and touch. This change in place necessarily needs to occur before the alteration in the sense that the alterer and what is altered are in contact only after locomotion has occurred.32 If one takes it that the example of the cold becoming hot refers to the process in which food is heated in order to become a part of the body (and that in this way the thought from the first part of the argument is contin- ued), then one could explain what happens in this way:33 the food, as that alteration in general. For, as I shall argue in the next chapter, Aristotle clearly holds the view that every alteration involves a change with respect to the subject’s affections. For instance he thinks that health is connected to heat (see Phys. IV 3, 210b24–27) and therefore also that a change from being healthy to being sick— which according to Cat. 8 would count as a change in a ἕξις, i.e. in quality—involves the subject’s change with respect to the qualities of hot and cold. This is also clear from the fact that any alteration may be partly characterised as a change in respect of tangible qualities (κατὰ γὰρ τὰ τῶν ἁπτῶν πάθη ἡ ἀλλοίωσις ἐστιν, GC ΙΙ 4, 331a9–10), that again may be explained in terms of the four basic qualities of hot, cold, dry, and moist. I will argue for the claim that alteration in general involves a change in the respective thing’s affection later on in section 4.4.3. 30 λέγω […] ἅπτεσθαι δὲ ὧν τὰ ἄκρα ἅμα. Phys. V 3, 226b20–227a7: “I say that things are touching if their extremes are together.” 31 δῆλον οὖν ὅτι τὸ κινοῦν οὐχ ὁμοίως ἔχει, ἀλλ᾽ ὁτὲ μὲν ἐγγύτερον ὁτὲ δὲ πορρώ- τερον τοῦ ἀλλοιουμένου ἐστίν. Phys. VIII 7, 260b1–3. 32 In fact it is not only the case for alteration that what causes the respective change (τὸ κινοῦν) needs to be in contact with that which undergoes the change (τὸ κινούμενον), but also for locomotion (243a11–244b2), and for growth and diminution (see 245a11–16), that is, for all three kinds of non-substantial change (243a34–35). It is puzzling that Aristotle does not simply make use of this fact to show that change in magnitude also presupposes locomo- tion in the same sense as alteration does. The only reason I can think of is that Aristotle for some reason not only wants to show that locomotion is prior to change in quality and quan- tity, but also that alteration is prior to growth and diminution. 33 This is what Simplicius, In Phys. 8, 1265–1266, thinks. One could also think, however, that Aristotle, by using the pair of hot and cold, is referring to two of the four basic qualities which, apart from dry and moist, (which as we saw are used in the explanation of growth in GC I 5 and de An. II 4) are involved in any alteration, as they characterise the basic material components of all composite substances in the sublunary sphere. (For more on this see my discussion of the second argument, esp. section 4.4.3). Growth and diminution presuppose alteration 51 ISBN Print: 9783525253069 — ISBN E-Book: 9783647253060 © 2014, Vandenhoeck & Ruprecht GmbH & Co. KG, Göttingen
zurück zum  Buch The Priority of Locomotion in Aristotle’s Physics"
The Priority of Locomotion in Aristotle’s Physics
Titel
The Priority of Locomotion in Aristotle’s Physics
Autor
Sebastian Odzuck
Herausgeber
Dorothea Frede
Gisela Striker
Verlag
Vandenhoeck & Ruprecht GmbH & Co
Datum
2014
Sprache
englisch
Lizenz
CC BY-NC-ND 4.0
ISBN
9783647253060
Abmessungen
15.5 x 23.2 cm
Seiten
238
Kategorien
Geisteswissenschaften
Naturwissenschaften Physik

Inhaltsverzeichnis

  1. Acknowledgements 9
  2. 1. Introduction 10
  3. 2. The importance of the primary kind of change 14
    1. 2.1 Overview 14
    2. 2.2 The arrangement of the Physics 15
      1. 2.2.1 First option: Books VI–VIII as the treatise On Change 18
        1. 2.2.1.1 Andronicus 19
        2. 2.2.1.2 Theophrastus’ letter 19
        3. 2.2.1.3 References in Aristotle 21
        4. 2.2.1.4 Eudemus 21
      2. 2.2.2 Second option: Books V–VIII as the treatise On Change 22
    3. 2.3 The eight books of the Physics 25
      1. 2.3.1 Physics I–IV: Examining change for the sake of understanding nature 25
      2. 2.3.2 Physics V–VIII: The general analysis of change 27
    4. 2.4 Physics VIII 31
      1. 2.4.1 Overview 31
      2. 2.4.2 The argument of Physics VIII 31
      3. 2.4.3 The importance of the primary kind of change 34
    5. 2.5 Conclusion 40
  4. 3. Change in quality and quantity of living beings depends on loco-motion, but not vice versa 42
    1. 3.1 Overview 42
    2. 3.2 Growth and diminution presuppose alteration 44
      1. 3.2.1 Growth presupposes alteration 45
      2. 3.2.2 Diminution presupposes alteration 48
    3. 3.3 Alteration presupposes locomotion 49
    4. 3.4 Does locomotion precede all occurrences of change in quantity? 53
    5. 3.5 The reason for the restriction of the argument’s scope 58
    6. 3.6 The sense of priority 67
    7. 3.7 Conclusion 69
  5. 4. Locomotion necessarily accompanies each of the other kinds of change, but not vice versa 71
    1. 4.1 Overview 71
    2. 4.2 What changes in quantity changes with respect to place 73
      1. 4.2.1 Overview 73
      2. 4.2.2 What is growing moves to a larger place 74
      3. 4.2.3 Change in place implies no change in the spatial order of the subject’s parts 78
      4. 4.2.4 A possible objection 81
      5. 4.2.5 Compatibility with the irreducibility of the kinds of change 85
      6. 4.2.6 Conclusion 88
    3. 4.3 What undergoes generation or corruption changes with respect to place 89
      1. 4.3.1 Overview 89
      2. 4.3.2 Generation and corruption in virtue of aggregation and segregation 90
      3. 4.3.3 What aggregates or segregates must change with respect to place 96
      4. 4.3.4 Conclusion 97
    4. 4.4 What changes in quality changes with respect to place 98
      1. 4.4.1 Overview 98
      2. 4.4.2 What does it mean that condensation and rarefaction are principles of quality? 100
      3. 4.4.3 Every alteration involves a change in the four basic qualities 104
      4. 4.4.4 Every change in the four basic qualities involves con- densation or rarefaction 108
      5. 4.4.5 Condensation and rarefaction are forms of aggregation and segregation 110
      6. 4.4.6 What changes in quality changes with respect to place 112
      7. 4.4.7 Conclusion 113
    5. 4.5 Conclusion 113
  6. 5. All changes depend on the first locomotion, but not vice versa 115
    1. 5.1 Overview 115
    2. 5.2 The unity of the eternal change 118
      1. 5.2.1 Two ways in which change may be eternal 118
      2. 5.2.2 Why the eternal change must be one and continuous 121
      3. 5.2.3 The criteria for being one continuous change 123
      4. 5.2.4 What is better is the case in nature 127
    3. 5.3 Locomotion alone can be one and eternal 130
      1. 5.3.1 None of the other three kinds of change can be one and eternal 131
      2. 5.3.2 Only circular locomotion can be one and eternal 134
    4. 5.4 Locomotion has ontological priority 137
      1. 5.4.1 Ontological priority 137
      2. 5.4.2 A third sense in which locomotion is ontologically prior 139
    5. 5.5 Conclusion 142
  7. 6. Locomotion has temporal priority 144
    1. 6.1 Overview 144
    2. 6.2 Locomotion has priority in time, since it is the only change eternals can undergo 146
    3. 6.3 Objection: Locomotion is the last of all changes in perishable things 148
    4. 6.4 Coming to be presupposes an earlier locomotion 150
    5. 6.5 The locomotion of the sun as a cause of generation 154
    6. 6.6 Conclusion 162
  8. 7. Locomotion is prior in essence 164
    1. 7.1 Locomotion is prior in essence, since it is last in coming to be 164
      1. 7.1.1 Overview 164
      2. 7.1.2 The reversed priority claim 166
      3. 7.1.3 A different use of the term ‘locomotion’ 172
      4. 7.1.4 Does locomotion come to things last? 175
        1. 7.1.4.1 Capacities of the soul 176
        2. 7.1.4.2 Priority in essence of the locomotive capacity 179
      5. 7.1.5 Another sense of priority in essence 182
      6. 7.1.6 Conclusion 184
    2. 7.2 Locomotion alone preserves its subject’s essence 186
      1. 7.2.1 Overview 186
      2. 7.2.2 Locomotion does not change its subject’s being 188
      3. 7.2.3 Locomotion preserves its subject’s essence best 190
      4. 7.2.4 Making x depart from its essence by being part of a change in essence? 195
        1. 7.2.4.1 Alteration as part of a change in essence 195
        2. 7.2.4.2 Growth and diminution as part of change in essence 199
        3. 7.2.4.3 Locomotion as a part of a change in essence? 201
      5. 7.2.5 Change in quality or quantity in principle may result in a change in essence 202
    3. 7.3 Conclusion: Locomotion’s priority in essence 207
  9. 8. Conclusion 211
  10. Bibliography 220
  11. List of Abbreviations 223
  12. Index Locorum 221
  13. Index Nominum 223
  14. Index Rerum 221
Web-Books
Bibliothek
Datenschutz
Impressum
Austria-Forum
Austria-Forum
Web-Books
The Priority of Locomotion in Aristotle’s Physics